Perfect preimages of Lindelof spaces

Let f:X \rightarrow Y be a mapping from a topological space X onto a topological space Y. If f is a perfect map and Y is a Lindelof space, then so is X. If f is a closed map and Y is a paracompact space, then so is X. In other words, the pre-image of a Lindelof space under a perfect map is always a Lindelof space. Likewise, the pre-image of a paracompact space under a closed map is always a paracompact space. After proving these two facts, we show that for any compact space Y, the product X \times Y is Lindelof (paracompact) for any Lindelof (paracompact) space X. All spaces under consideration are Hausdorff.

Another way to state the above two facts is that Lindelofness is an inverse invariance under perfect maps and that paracompactness is an inverse invariance of the closed maps. In general, a topological property is an inverse invariance of a class of mappings \mathcal{M} if the following holds: for any mapping f:X \rightarrow Y belonging to \mathcal{M}, if Y has the property, then so does X. In contrast, a topological property is an invariance of a class of mappings \mathcal{M} if for any mapping f:X \rightarrow Y belonging to \mathcal{M}, if X has the property, then so does Y.

All mappings under consideration are continuous maps. A mapping f:X \rightarrow Y, where f(X)=Y, is a closed map if for any closed subset A of X, f(A) is closed in Y. A mapping f:X \rightarrow Y, where f(X)=Y, is a perfect map if f is a closed map and that the point inverse f^{-1}(y) is compact for each y \in Y.

Perfect mappings and closed mappings are objects with strong properties. Such a map places a restriction on what topological properties the “domain” space or the “range” space can have. The theorems below indicate that it is not possible to map a non-Lindelof space onto a Lindelof space using a perfect map and that it is not possible to map a non-paracompact space onto a paracompact space using a closed map. On the other hand, it is not possible to map a separable metric space onto a separable but non-metric space using a perfect map (see here). We prove the following theorems.

Theorem 1…. Lindelofness (or the Lindelof property) is an inverse invariant of the perfect maps.

Theorem 2 ….Paracompactness is an inverse invariant of the closed maps.

Lemma 3 …. Let f:X \longrightarrow Y be a closed map with f(X)=Y. Let V be an open subset of X. Define f_*(V)=\{ y \in Y: f^{-1}(y) \subset V \}. Then the set f_*(V) is open in Y and that f_*(V) \subset f(V).

For the proof of Lemma 3, see Lemma 2 here.

Proof of Theorem 1
Let f:X \longrightarrow Y be a perfect map with f(X)=Y. Suppose Y is Lindelof. Let \mathcal{U} be an open cover of X. Without loss of generality, we can assume that \mathcal{U} is closed under finite unions. For each U \in \mathcal{U}, define f_*(U)=\{ y \in Y: f^{-1}(y) \subset U \}. By Lemma 3, each f_*(U) is an open subset of Y. We claim that \mathcal{V}=\{ f_*(U): U \in \mathcal{U} \} is an open cover of Y. To this end, let y \in Y. Since f is a perfect map, the point inverse f^{-1}(y) is compact. As a result, we can find a finite \mathcal{F} \subset \mathcal{U} such that f^{-1}(y) \subset \bigcup \mathcal{F}=W. Since \mathcal{U} is closed under finite unions, W \in \mathcal{U}. It follows that y \in f_*(W). Since Y is Lindelof, there exists a countable \{W_0,W_1,W_2,\cdots \} \subset \mathcal{V} such that Y = \bigcup_{n=0}^\infty W_n. For each n, W_n=f_*(U_n) for some U_n \in \mathcal{U}. We claim that \{U_0,U_1,U_2,\cdots \} is a cover of X. To this end, let x \in X. Then for some n, y=f(x) \in W_n=f_*(U_n). This implies that x \in f^{-1}(y) \subset U_n. Thus, the open cover \mathcal{U} has a countable subcover. This concludes the proof of Theorem 1. \square

Proof of Theorem 2
Let f:X \longrightarrow Y be a perfect map with f(X)=Y. Suppose Y is paracompact. Let \mathcal{U} be an open cover of X. For each U \in \mathcal{U}, define f_*(U) as in Lemma 3. By Lemma 3, each f_*(U) is an open subset of Y. Let \mathcal{V}=\{ f_*(U): U \in \mathcal{U} \}. As shown in the proof of Theorem 1, \mathcal{V} is an open cover of Y. Since Y is paracompact, there exists a locally finite open refinement \mathcal{W} of \mathcal{V}. Let \mathcal{W}_0=\{ f^{-1}(W): W \in \mathcal{W} \}.

We show three facts about \mathcal{W}_0. (1) It is an open cover of X. (2) It is a locally finite collection in X. (3) It is a refinement of \mathcal{U}. To see (1), note that \mathcal{W} is an open cover of Y. As a result, \mathcal{W}_0 is an open cover of X. To see (2), let x \in X. We find an open O \subset X such that x \in O and such that O intersects only finitely many elements of \mathcal{W}_0. Since \mathcal{W} is locally finite in Y, there exists an open B \subset Y such that y=f(x) \in B and such that B intersects only finitely many elements of \mathcal{W}, say, W_0,W_1,\cdots,W_n. Let O=f^{-1}(B). Clearly, x \in O. It can be verified that the only elements of \mathcal{W}_0 having non-empty intersections with O are f^{-1}(W_0),f^{-1}(W_1),\cdots,f^{-1}(W_n). To see (3), let f^{-1}(W) \in \mathcal{W}_0 where W \in \mathcal{W}. Then W \subset V=f_*(U) for some V \in \mathcal{V} and some U \in \mathcal{U}. We claim that f^{-1}(W) \subset U. Let x \in f^{-1}(W). Then y=f(x) \in W \subset V=f_*(U). This implies that x \in f^{-1}(y) \subset U. It follows that \mathcal{W}_0 is a locally finite open refinement of the open cover \mathcal{U}. This completes the proof of Theorem 2. \square

Productively Paracompact Spaces

A space X is productively paramcompact if X \times Y is paracompact for every paracompact space Y. The definition for productively Lindelof can be stated in a similar way. For some reason, the term “productively paracompact” is not used in the literature but is a topic that had been extensively studied. It is also a topic found in this site. The following four classes of spaces are productively paracompact (see here and here).

  • Compact spaces
  • \sigma-compact spaces
  • Locally compact spaces
  • \sigma-locally compact spaces

The proof for compact spaces being productively paracompact given here uses the Tube Lemma (see here). As applications of Theorem 1 and Theorem 2, we use the two theorems to show that compact spaces are both productively Lindelof and productive paracompact.

Theorem 4…. Let Y any compact space. Then X \times Y is Lindelof for every Lindelof space X.

Theorem 5 ….Let Y any compact space. Then X \times Y is paracompact for every paracompact space X.

Theorems 4 and 5 are corollaries to the Kuratowski theorem (see here) and Theorems 1 and 2 above. Suppose Y is compact. Then the projection map from X \times Y onto X is a closed map. The paracompactness of X \times Y follows whenever X is paracompact. The projection map is also perfect since the point inverses are compact due to the compactness of the factor Y. Then the Lindelofness of X \times Y follows whenever X is Lindelof.

\text{ }

\text{ }

\text{ }

Dan Ma invariant
Daniel Ma invariant

Dan Ma Inverse invariant
Daniel Ma Inverse invariant

Dan Ma perfect map
Daniel Ma perfect map

Dan Ma paracompact space
Daniel Ma paracompact space

Dan Ma Lindelof space
Daniel Ma Lindelof space

Dan Ma topology
Daniel Ma topology

\copyright 2023 – Dan Ma

The product of locally compact paracompact spaces

It is well known that when X and Y are paracompact spaces, the product space X \times Y is not necessarily normal. Classic examples include the product of the Sorgenfrey line with itself (discussed here) and the product of the Michael line and the space of irrational numbers (discussed here). However, if one of the paracompact factors is “compact”, the product can be normal or even paracompact. This post discusses several classic results along this line. All spaces are Hausdorff and regular.

Suppose that X and Y are paracompact spaces. We have the following results:

  1. If Y is a compact space, then X \times Y is paracompact.
  2. If Y is a \sigma-compact space, then X \times Y is paracompact.
  3. If Y is a locally compact space, then X \times Y is paracompact.
  4. If Y is a \sigma-locally compact space, then X \times Y is paracompact.

The proof of the first result makes uses the tube lemma. The second result is a corollary of the first. The proofs of both results are given here. The third result is a corollary of the fourth result. We give a proof of the fourth result.

____________________________________________________________________

Proof of the Fourth Result

The fourth result indicated above is restated as Theorem 2 below. It is a theorem of K. Morita [1]. This is one classic result on product of paracompact spaces. After proving the theorem, comments are made about interesting facts and properties that follow from this result. Theorem 2 is also Theorem 3.22 in chapter 18 in the Handbook of Set-Theoretic Topology [2].

A space W is a locally compact space if for each w \in W, there is an open subset O of W such that w \in O and \overline{O} is compact. When we say Y is a \sigma-locally compact space, we mean that Y=\bigcup_{j=1}^\infty Y_j where each Y_j is a locally compact space. In proving the result discussed here, we also assume that each Y_j is a closed subspace of Y. The following lemma will be helpful.

Lemma 1
Let Y be a paracompact space. Suppose that Y is \sigma-locally compact. Then there exists a cover \mathcal{C}=\bigcup_{j=1}^\infty \mathcal{C}_j of Y such that each \mathcal{C}_j is a locally finite family consisting of compact sets.

Proof of Lemma 1
Let Y=\bigcup_{n=1}^\infty Y_n such that each Y_n is closed and is locally compact. Fix an integer n. For each y \in Y_n, let O_{n,y} be an open subset of Y_n such that y \in O_{n,y} and \overline{O_{n,y}} is compact (the closure is taken in Y_n). Consider the open cover \mathcal{O}=\left\{ O_{n,y}: y \in Y_j \right\} of Y_n. Since Y_n is a closed subspace of Y, Y_n is also paracompact. Let \mathcal{V}=\left\{ V_{n,y}: y \in Y_j \right\} be a locally finite open cover of Y_n such that \overline{V_{n,y}} \subset O_{n,y} for each y \in Y_n (again the closure is taken in Y_n). Each \overline{V_{n,y}} is compact since \overline{V_{n,y}} \subset O_{n,y} \subset \overline{O_{n,y}}. Let \mathcal{C}_n=\left\{ \overline{V_{n,y}}: y \in Y_n \right\}.

We claim that \mathcal{C}_n is a locally finite family with respect to the space Y. For each y \in Y-Y_n, Y-Y_n is an open set containing y that intersects no set in \mathcal{C}_n. For each y \in Y_n, there is an open set O \subset Y_n that meets only finitely many sets in \mathcal{C}_n. Extend O to an open subset O_1 of Y. That is, O_1 is an open subset of Y such that O=O_1 \cap Y_n. It is clear that O_1 can only meets finitely many sets in \mathcal{C}_n.

Then \mathcal{C}=\bigcup_{j=1}^\infty \mathcal{C}_j is the desired \sigma-locally finite cover of Y. \square

Theorem 2
Let X be any paracompact space and let Y be any \sigma-locally compact paracompact space. Then X \times Y is paracompact.

Proof of Theorem 2
By Lemma 1, let \mathcal{C}=\bigcup_{n=1}^\infty \mathcal{C}_n be a \sigma-locally finite cover of Y such that each \mathcal{C}_n consists of compact sets. To show that X \times Y is paracompact, let \mathcal{U} be an open cover of X \times Y. For each C \in \mathcal{C} and for each x \in X, the set \left\{ x \right\} \times C is obviously compact.

Fix C \in \mathcal{C} and fix x \in X. For each y \in C, the point (x,y) \in U_{y} for some U_{y} \in \mathcal{U}. Choose open H_y \subset X and open K_y \subset Y such that (x,y) \in H_y \times K_y \subset U_{x,y}. Letting y vary, the open sets H_y \times K_y cover the compact set \left\{ x \right\} \times C. Choose finitely many open sets H_y \times K_y that also cover \left\{ x \right\} \times C. Let H(C,x) be the intersection of these finitely many H_y. Let \mathcal{K}(C,x) be the set of these finitely many K_y.

To summarize what we have obtained in the previous paragraph, for each C \in \mathcal{C} and for each x \in X, there exists an open subset H(C,x) containing x, and there exists a finite set \mathcal{K}(C,x) of open subsets of Y such that

  • C \subset \bigcup \mathcal{K}(C,x),
  • for each K \in \mathcal{K}(C,x), H(C,x) \times K \subset U for some U \in \mathcal{U}.

For each C \in \mathcal{C}, the set of all H(C,x) is an open cover of X. Since X is paracompact, for each C \in \mathcal{C}, there exists a locally finite open cover \mathcal{L}_C=\left\{L(C,x): x \in X \right\} such that L(C,x) \subset H(C,x) for all x. Consider the following families of open sets.

    \mathcal{E}_n=\left\{L(C,x) \times K: C \in \mathcal{C}_n \text{ and } x \in X \text{ and } K \in \mathcal{K}(C,x) \right\}

    \mathcal{E}=\bigcup_{n=1}^\infty \mathcal{E}_n

We claim that \mathcal{E} is a \sigma-locally finite open refinement of \mathcal{U}. First, show that \mathcal{E} is an open cover of X \times Y. Let (a,b) \in X \times Y. Then for some n, b \in C for some C \in \mathcal{C}_n. Furthermore, a \in L(C,x) for some x \in X. The information about C and x are detailed above. For example, C \subset \bigcup \mathcal{K}(C,x). Thus there exists some K \in \mathcal{K}(C,x) such that b \in K. We now have (a,b) \in L(C,x) \times K \in \mathcal{E}_n.

Next we show that \mathcal{E} is a refinement of \mathcal{U}. Fix L(C,x) \times K \in \mathcal{E}_n. Immediately we see that L(C,x) \subset H(C,x). Since K \in \mathcal{K}(C,x), H(C,x) \times K \subset U for some U \in \mathcal{U}. Then L(C,x) \times K \subset U.

The remaining point to make is that each \mathcal{E}_n is a locally finite family of open subsets of X \times Y. Let (a,b) \in X \times Y. Since \mathcal{C}_n is locally finite in Y, there exists some open Q \subset Y such that b \in Q and Q meets only finitely many sets in \mathcal{C}_n, say C_1,C_2,\cdots,C_m. Recall that \mathcal{L}_{C_j} is the set of all L(C_j,x) and is locally finite. Thus there exists an open O \subset X such that a \in O and O meets only finitely many sets in each \mathcal{L}_{C_j} where j=1,2,\cdots,m. Thus the open set O meets only finitely many sets L(C,x) for finitely many C \in \mathcal{C}_n and finitely many x \in X. These finitely many C and x lead to finitely many K. Thus it follows that O \times Q meets only finitely many sets L(C,x) \times K in \mathcal{E}_n. Thus \mathcal{E}_n is locally finite.

What has been established is that every open cover of X \times Y has a \sigma-locally finite open refinement. This fact is equivalent to paracompactness (according to Theorem 1 in this previous post). This concludes the proof of the theorem. \square

____________________________________________________________________

Productively Paracompact Spaces

Consider this property for a space X.

    (*) The space X satisfies the property that X \times Y is a paracompact space for every paracompact space Y.

Such a space can be called a productively paracompact space (for some reason, this term is not used in the literature).

According to the four results stated at the beginning, any space in any one of the following four classes

  1. Compact spaces.
  2. \sigma-compact spaces.
  3. Locally compact paracompact spaces.
  4. \sigma-locally compact paracompact spaces.

satisfies this property. Both the Michael line and the space of the irrational numbers are examples of paracompact spaces that do not have this productively paracompact property. According to comments made on page 799 [2], the theorem of Morita (Theorem 2 here) triggered extensive research to investigate this class of spaces. The class of spaces is broader than the four classes listed here. For example, the productively paracompact spaces also include the closed images of locally compact paracompact spaces. The handbook [2] has more references.

____________________________________________________________________

Normal P-Spaces

Consider this property.

    (**) The space X satisfies the property that X \times Y is a normal space for every metric space Y.

These spaces can be called productively normal spaces with respect to metric spaces. They go by another name. Morita defined the notion of P-spaces and proved that a space X is a normal P-space if and only if the product of X with any metric space is normal.

Since the class of metric spaces contain the paracompact spaces, any space has property (*) would have property (**), i.e. a normal P-space.Thus any locally compact paracompact space is a normal P-space. Any \sigma-locally compact paracompact space is a normal P-space. If a paracompact space has any one of the four “compact” properties discussed here, it is a normal P-space.

Other examples of normal P-spaces are countably compact normal spaces (see here) and perfectly normal spaces (see here).

____________________________________________________________________

Looking at Diagrams

Let’s compare these classes of spaces: productively paracompact spaces (the spaces satisfying property (*)), normal P-spaces and paracompact spaces. We have the following diagram.

    Diagram 1

    \displaystyle \begin{array}{ccccc} \text{ } &\text{ } & \text{Productively Paracompact} & \text{ } & \text{ } \\  \text{ } & \swarrow & \text{ } & \searrow & \text{ } \\  \text{Paracompact} &\text{ } & \text{ } & \text{ } & \text{Normal P-space} \\     \text{ } & \text{ } & \text{ } & \text{ } & \text{ } \\    \end{array}

Clearly productively paracompact implies paracompact. As discussed in the previous section, productively paracompact implies normal P. If a space X is such that the product of X with every paracompact space is paracompact, then the product of X with every metric space is paracompact and hence normal.

However, the arrows in Diagram 1 are not reversible. The Michael line mentioned at the beginning will shed some light on this point. Here’s the previous post on Michael line. Let \mathbb{M} be the Michael line. Let \mathbb{P} be the space of the irrational numbers. The space \mathbb{M} would be a paracompact space that is not productively paracompact since its product with \mathbb{P} is not normal, hence not paracompact.

On the other hand, the space of irrational numbers \mathbb{P} is a normal P-space since it is a metric space. But it is not productively paracompact since its product with the Michael line \mathbb{M} is not normal, hence not paracompact.

The two classes of spaces at the bottom of Diagram 1 do not relate. The Michael line \mathbb{M} is a paracompact space that is not a normal P-space since its product with \mathbb{P} is not normal. Normal P-space does not imply paracompact. Any space that is normal and countably compact is a normal P-space. For example, the space \omega_1, the first uncountable ordinal, with the ordered topology is normal and countably compact and is not paracompact.

There are other normal P-spaces that are not paracompact. For example, Bing’s Example H is perfectly normal and not paracompact. As mentioned in the previous section, any perfectly normal space is a normal P-space.

The class of spaces whose product with every paracompact space is paracompact is stronger than both classes of paracompact spaces and normal P-spaces. It is a strong property and an interesting class of spaces. It is also an excellent topics for any student who wants to dig deeper into paracompact spaces.

Let’s add one more property to Diagram 1.

    Diagram 2

    \displaystyle \begin{array}{ccccc} \text{ } &\text{ } & \text{Productively Paracompact} & \text{ } & \text{ } \\  \text{ } & \swarrow & \text{ } & \searrow & \text{ } \\  \text{Paracompact} &\text{ } & \text{ } & \text{ } & \text{Normal P-space} \\   \text{ } & \searrow & \text{ } & \swarrow & \text{ } \\  \text{ } &\text{ } & \text{Normal Countably Paracompact} & \text{ } & \text{ } \\     \text{ } & \text{ } & \text{ } & \text{ } & \text{ } \\    \end{array}

All properties in Diagram 2 except for paracompact are productive. Normal countably paracompact spaces are productive. According to Dowker’s theorem, the product of any normal countably paracompact space with any compact metric space is normal (see Theorem 1 in this previous post). The last two arrows in Diagram 2 are also not reversible.

____________________________________________________________________

Reference

  1. Morita K., On the Product of Paracompact Spaces, Proc. Japan Acad., Vol. 39, 559-563, 1963.
  2. Przymusinski T. C., Products of Normal Spaces, Handbook of Set-Theoretic Topology (K. Kunen and J. E. Vaughan, eds), Elsevier Science Publishers B. V., Amsterdam, 781-826, 1984.

____________________________________________________________________
\copyright 2017 – Dan Ma

An example of a normal but not Lindelof Cp(X)

In this post, we discuss an example of a function space C_p(X) that is normal and not Lindelof (as indicated in the title). Interestingly, much more can be said about this function space. In this post, we show that there exists a space X such that

  • C_p(X) is collectionwise normal and not paracompact,
  • C_p(X) is not Lindelof but contains a dense Lindelof subspace,
  • C_p(X) is not first countable but is a Frechet space,
  • As a corollary of the previous point, C_p(X) cannot contain a copy of the compact space \omega_1+1,
  • C_p(X) is homeomorphic to C_p(X)^\omega,
  • C_p(X) is not hereditarily normal,
  • C_p(X) is not metacompact.

A short and quick description of the space X is that X is the one-point Lindelofication of an uncountable discrete space. As shown below, the function space C_p(X) is intimately related to a \Sigma-product of copies of real lines. The results listed above are merely an introduction to this wonderful example and are derived by examining the \Sigma-products of copies of real lines. Deep results about \Sigma-product of real lines abound in the literature. The references listed at the end are a small sample. Example 3.2 in [2] is another interesting illustration of this example.

We now define the domain space X=L_\tau. In the discussion that follows, the Greek letter \tau is always an uncountable cardinal number. Let D_\tau be a set with cardinality \tau. Let p be a point not in D_\tau. Let L_\tau=D_\tau \cup \left\{p \right\}. Consider the following topology on L_\tau:

  • Each point in D_\tau an isolated point, and
  • open neighborhoods at the point p are of the form L_\tau-K where K \subset D_\tau is countable.

It is clear that L_\tau is a Lindelof space. The Lindelof space L_\tau is sometimes called the one-point Lindelofication of the discrete space D_\tau since it is a Lindelof space that is obtained by adding one point to a discrete space.

Consider the function space C_p(L_\tau). See this post for general information on the pointwise convergence topology of C_p(Y) for any completely regular space Y.

All the facts about C_p(X)=C_p(L_\tau) mentioned at the beginning follow from the fact that C_p(L_\tau) is homeomorphic to the \Sigma-product of \tau many copies of the real lines. Specifically, C_p(L_\tau) is homeomorphic to the following subspace of the product space \mathbb{R}^\tau.

    \Sigma_{\alpha<\tau}\mathbb{R}=\left\{ x \in \mathbb{R}^\tau: x_\alpha \ne 0 \text{ for at most countably many } \alpha<\tau \right\}

Thus understanding the function space C_p(L_\tau) is a matter of understanding a \Sigma-product of copies of the real lines. First, we establish the homeomorphism and then discuss the properties of C_p(L_\tau) indicated above.

____________________________________________________________________

The Homeomorphism

For each f \in C_p(L_\tau), it is easily seen that there is a countable set C \subset D_\tau such that f(p)=f(y) for all y \in D_\tau-C. Let W_0=\left\{f \in C_p(L_\tau): f(p)=0 \right\}. Then each f \in W_0 has non-zero values only on a countable subset of D_\tau. Naturally, W_0 and \Sigma_{\alpha<\tau}\mathbb{R} are homeomorphic.

We claim that C_p(L_\tau) is homeomorphic to W_0 \times \mathbb{R}. For each f \in C_p(L_\tau), define h(f)=(f-f(p),f(p)). Here, f-f(p) is the function g \in C_p(L_\tau) such that g(x)=f(x)-f(p) for all x \in L_\tau. Clearly h(f) is well-defined and h(f) \in W_0 \times \mathbb{R}. It can be readily verified that h is a one-to-one map from C_p(L_\tau) onto W_0 \times \mathbb{R}. It is not difficult to verify that both h and h^{-1} are continuous.

We use the notation X_1 \cong X_2 to mean that the spaces X_1 and X_2 are homeomorphic. Then we have:

    C_p(L_\tau) \ \cong \ W_0 \times \mathbb{R} \ \cong \ (\Sigma_{\alpha<\tau}\mathbb{R})  \times \mathbb{R} \ \cong \ \Sigma_{\alpha<\tau}\mathbb{R}

Thus C_p(L_\tau) \ \cong \ \Sigma_{\alpha<\tau}\mathbb{R}. This completes the proof that C_p(L_\tau) is topologically the \Sigma-product of \tau many copies of the real lines.

____________________________________________________________________

Looking at the \Sigma-Product

Understanding the function space C_p(L_\tau) is now reduced to the problem of understanding a \Sigma-product of copies of the real lines. Most of the facts about \Sigma-products that we need have already been proved in previous blog posts.

In this previous post, it is established that the \Sigma-product of separable metric spaces is collectionwise normal. Thus C_p(L_\tau) is collectionwise normal. The \Sigma-product of spaces, each of which has at least two points, always contains a closed copy of \omega_1 with the ordered topology (see the lemma in this previous post). Thus C_p(L_\tau) contains a closed copy of \omega_1 and hence can never be paracompact (and thus not Lindelof).

___________________________________

Consider the following subspace of the \Sigma-product \Sigma_{\alpha<\tau}\mathbb{R}:

    \sigma_\tau=\left\{ x \in \Sigma_{\alpha<\tau}\mathbb{R}: x_\alpha \ne 0 \text{ for at most finitely many } \alpha<\tau \right\}

In this previous post, it is shown that \sigma_\tau is a Lindelof space. Though C_p(L_\tau) \cong \Sigma_{\alpha<\tau}\mathbb{R} is not Lindelof, it has a dense Lindelof subspace, namely \sigma_\tau.

___________________________________

A space Y is first countable if there exists a countable local base at each point y \in Y. A space Y is a Frechet space (or is Frechet-Urysohn) if for each y \in Y, if y \in \overline{A} where A \subset Y, then there exists a sequence \left\{y_n: n=1,2,3,\cdots \right\} of points of A such that the sequence converges to y. Clearly, any first countable space is a Frechet space. The converse is not true (see Example 1 in this previous post).

For any uncountable cardinal number \tau, the product \mathbb{R}^\tau is not first countable. In fact, any dense subspace of \mathbb{R}^\tau is not first countable. In particular, the \Sigma-product \Sigma_{\alpha<\tau}\mathbb{R} is not first countable. In this previous post, it is shown that the \Sigma-product of first countable spaces is a Frechet space. Thus C_p(L_\tau) \cong \Sigma_{\alpha<\tau}\mathbb{R} is a Frechet space.

___________________________________

As a corollary of the previous point, C_p(L_\tau) \cong \Sigma_{\alpha<\tau}\mathbb{R} cannot contain a homeomorphic copy of any space that is not Frechet. In particular, it cannot contain a copy of any compact space that is not Frechet. For example, the compact space \omega_1+1 is not embeddable in C_p(L_\tau). The interest in compact subspaces of C_p(L_\tau) \cong \Sigma_{\alpha<\tau}\mathbb{R} is that any compact space that is topologically embeddable in a \Sigma-product of real lines is said to be Corson compact. Thus any Corson compact space is a Frechet space.

___________________________________

It can be readily verified that

    \Sigma_{\alpha<\tau}\mathbb{R} \ \cong \ \Sigma_{\alpha<\tau}\mathbb{R} \ \times \ \Sigma_{\alpha<\tau}\mathbb{R} \ \times \ \Sigma_{\alpha<\tau}\mathbb{R} \ \times \ \cdots \ \text{(countably many times)}

Thus C_p(L_\tau) \cong C_p(L_\tau)^\omega. In particular, C_p(L_\tau) \cong C_p(L_\tau) \times C_p(L_\tau) due to the following observation:

    C_p(L_\tau) \times C_p(L_\tau) \cong C_p(L_\tau)^\omega \times C_p(L_\tau)^\omega \cong C_p(L_\tau)^\omega \cong C_p(L_\tau)

___________________________________

As a result of the peculiar fact that C_p(L_\tau) \cong C_p(L_\tau) \times C_p(L_\tau), it can be concluded that C_p(L_\tau), though normal, is not hereditarily normal. This follows from an application of Katetov’s theorem. The theorem states that if Y_1 \times Y_2 is hereditarily normal, then either Y_1 is perfectly normal or every countably infinite subset of Y_2 is closed and discrete (see this previous post). The function space C_p(L _\tau) is not perfectly normal since it contains a closed copy of \omega_1. On the other hand, there are plenty of countably infinite subsets of C_p(L _\tau) that are not closed and discrete. As a Frechet space, C_p(L _\tau) has many convergent sequences. Each such sequence without the limit is a countably infinite set that is not closed and discrete. As an example, let \left\{x_1,x_2,x_3,\cdots \right\} be an infinite subset of D_\tau and consider the following:

    C=\left\{f_n: n=1,2,3,\cdots \right\}

where f_n is such that f_n(x_n)=n and f_n(x)=0 for each x \in L_\tau with x \ne x_n. Note that C is not closed and not discrete since the points in C converge to g \in \overline{C} where g is the zero-function. Thus C_p(L_\tau) \cong C_p(L_\tau) \times C_p(L_\tau) is not hereditarily normal.

___________________________________

It is well known that collectionwise normal metacompact space is paracompact (see Theorem 5.3.3 in [4] where metacompact is referred to as weakly paracompact). Since C_p(L_\tau) is collectionwise normal and not paracompact, C_p(L_\tau) can never be metacompact.

____________________________________________________________________

Reference

  1. Arkhangelskii, A. V., Topological Function Spaces, Mathematics and Its Applications Series, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, 1992.
  2. Bella, A., Masami, S., Tight points of Pixley-Roy hyperspaces, Topology Appl., 160, 2061-2068, 2013.
  3. Corson, H. H., Normality in subsets of product spaces, Amer. J. Math., 81, 785-796, 1959.
  4. Engelking, R., General Topology, Revised and Completed edition, Heldermann Verlag, Berlin, 1989.

____________________________________________________________________

\copyright \ 2014 \text{ by Dan Ma}

A theorem about CCC spaces

It is a well known result in general topology that in any regular space with the countable chain condition, paracompactness and the Lindelof property are equivalent. The proof of this result hinges on one theorem about the spaces with the countable chain condition. In this post we are to put the spotlight on this theorem (Theorem 1 below) and then use it to prove a few results. These results indicate that in a space with the countable chain condition with some weaker covering property is either Lindelof or paracompact.

This post is centered on a theorem about the CCC property (Theorem 1 and Theorem 1a below). So it can be considered as a continuation of a previous post on CCC called Some basic properties of spaces with countable chain condition. The results that are derived from Theorem 1 are also found in [2]. But the theorem concerning CCC is only a small part of that paper among several other focuses. In this post, the exposition is to explain several interesting theorems that are derived from Theorem 1. One of the theorems is the statement that every locally compact metacompact perfectly normal space is paracompact, a theorem originally proved by Arhangelskii (see Theorem 11 below).

____________________________________________________________________

CCC Spaces

All spaces under consideration are at least T_1 and regular. A space X is said to have the countable chain condition (to have the CCC for short) if \mathcal{U} is a disjoint collection of non-empty open subsets of X (meaning that for any A,B \in \mathcal{U} with A \ne B, we have A \cap B=\varnothing), then \mathcal{U} is countable. In other words, in a space with the CCC, there cannot be uncountably many pairwise disjoint non-empty open sets. For ease of making a statement or stating a result, if X has the CCC, we also say that X is a CCC space or X is CCC.

____________________________________________________________________

A Theorem about CCC Spaces

The theorem of CCC spaces we want to discuss has to do with collections of open sets that are “nice”. We first define what we mean by nice. Let \mathcal{A} be a collection of non-empty subsets of the space X. The collection \mathcal{A} is said to be point-finite (point-countable) if each point of X belongs to only finitely (countably) many sets in \mathcal{A}.

Now we define what we mean by “nice” collection of open sets. The collection \mathcal{A} is said to be locally finite (locally countable) at a point x \in X if there exists an open set O \subset X with x \in O such that O meets at most finitely (countably) many sets in \mathcal{A}. The collection \mathcal{A} is said to be locally finite (locally countable) if it is locally finite (locally countable) at each x \in X.

The property of being a separable space implies the CCC. The reverse is not true. However the CCC property is still a very strong property. The CCC property is equivalent to the property that if a collection of non-empty open sets is “nice” on a dense set of points, then the collection of open sets is a countable collection. The following is a precise statement.

    Theorem 1

      Let X be a CCC space. Then if \mathcal{U} is a collection of non-empty open subsets of X such that the following set

        D(\mathcal{U})=\left\{x \in X: \mathcal{U} \text{ is locally-countable at } x \right\}

      is dense in the open subspace \bigcup \mathcal{U}, then \mathcal{U} must be countable.

The collections of open sets in the above theorem do not have to be open covers. However, if they are open covers, the theorem can tie CCC spaces with some covering properties. As long as the space has the CCC, any open cover that is locally-countable on a dense set must be countable. Looking at it in the contrapositive angle, in a CCC space, any uncountable open cover is not locally-countable in some open set.

Proof of Theorem 1
Let \mathcal{U} be a collection of open subsets of X such that the set D(\mathcal{U}) as defined above is dense in the open subspace \bigcup \mathcal{U}. We show that \mathcal{U} is countable. Suppose not.

For each U \in \mathcal{U}, since U \cap D(\mathcal{U}) \ne \varnothing, we can choose a non-empty open set f(U) \subset U such that f(U) has non-empty intersection with only countably many sets in \mathcal{U}. Let \mathcal{U}_f be the following collection:

    \mathcal{U}_f=\left\{f(U): U \in \mathcal{U} \right\}

For H,K \in \mathcal{U}_f, by a chain from H to K, we mean a finite collection

    \left\{W_1,W_2,\cdots,W_n \right\} \subset \mathcal{U}_f

such that H=W_1, K=W_n and W_j \cap W_{j+1} \ne \varnothing for any 1 \le j <n. For each open set W \in \mathcal{U}_f, define \mathcal{C}(W) and \mathcal{E}(W) as follows:

    \mathcal{C}(W)=\left\{V \in \mathcal{U}_f: \text{there exists a chain from } W \text{ to } V \right\}

    \mathcal{E}(W)=\bigcup \mathcal{C}(W)

One observation we make is that for W_1,W_2 \in \mathcal{U}_f, if \mathcal{E}(W_1) \cap \mathcal{E}(W_2) \ne \varnothing, then \mathcal{C}(W_1)=\mathcal{C}(W_2) and \mathcal{E}(W_1)=\mathcal{E}(W_2). So the distinct \mathcal{E}(W) are pairwise disjoint. Because the space X has the CCC, there can be only countably many distinct open sets \mathcal{E}(W). Thus there can be only countably many distinct collections \mathcal{C}(W).

Note that each \mathcal{C}(W) is a countable collection of open sets. Each V \in \mathcal{U}_f meets only countably many open sets in \mathcal{U}. So each V \in \mathcal{U}_f can meet only countably many sets in \mathcal{U}_f, since for each V \in \mathcal{U}_f, V \subset U for some U \in \mathcal{U}. Thus for each W \in \mathcal{U}_f, in considering all finite-length chain starting from W, there can be only countably many open sets in \mathcal{U}_f that can be linked to W. Thus \mathcal{C}(W) must be countable. In taking the union of all \mathcal{C}(W), we get back the collection \mathcal{U}_f. Thus we have:

    \mathcal{U}_f=\bigcup \limits_{W \in \mathcal{U}_f} \mathcal{C}(W)

Because the space X is CCC, there are only countably many distinct collections \mathcal{C}(W) in the above union. Each \mathcal{C}(W) is countable. So \mathcal{U}_f is a countable collection of open sets.

Furthermore, each U \in \mathcal{U} contains at least one set in \mathcal{U}_f. From the way we choose sets in \mathcal{U}_f, we see that for each V \in \mathcal{U}_f, V=f(U) \subset U for at most countably many U \in \mathcal{U}. The argument indicates that we have a one-to-countable mapping from \mathcal{U}_f to \mathcal{U}. Thus the original collection \mathcal{U} must be countable. \blacksquare

The property in Theorem 1 is actually equivalent to the CCC property. Just that the proof of Theorem 1 represents the hard direction that needs to be proved. Theorem 1 can be expanded to be the following theorem.

    Theorem 1a

      Let X be a space. Then the following conditions are equivalent.

      1. The space X has the CCC.
      2. If \mathcal{U} is a collection of non-empty open subsets of X such that the following set

          D(\mathcal{U})=\left\{x \in X: \mathcal{U} \text{ is locally-countable at } x \right\}

        is dense in the open subspace \bigcup \mathcal{U}, then \mathcal{U} must be countable.

      3. If \mathcal{U} is a collection of non-empty open subsets of X such that \mathcal{U} is locally-countable at every point in the open subspace \bigcup \mathcal{U}, then \mathcal{U} must be countable.

The direction 1 \rightarrow 2 has been proved above. The directions 2 \rightarrow 3 and 3 \rightarrow 1 are straightforward.

____________________________________________________________________

Tying Theorem 1 to “Nice” Open Covers

One easy application of Theorem 1 is to tie it to locally-finite and locally-countable open covers. We have the following theorem.

    Theorem 2

      In any CCC space, any locally-countable open cover must be countable. Thus any locally-finite open cover must also be countable.

Theorem 2 gives the well known result that any CCC paracompact space is Lindelof (see Theorem 5 below). In fact, Theorem 2 gives the result that any CCC para-Lindelof space is Lindelof (see Theorem 6 below). A space X is para-Lindelof if every open cover has a locally-countable open refinement.

Can Theorem 2 hold for point-finite covers (or point-countable covers)? The answer is no (see Example 1 below). With the additional property of having a Baire space, we have the following theorem.

    Theorem 3

      In any Baire space with the CCC, any point-finite open cover must be countable.

A Space X is a Baire space if U_1,U_2,U_3,\cdots are dense open subsets of X, then \bigcap \limits_{j=1}^\infty U_j \ne \varnothing. For more information about Baire spaces, see this previous post.
.

Proof of Theorem 3
Let X be a Baire space with the CCC. Let \mathcal{U} be a point-finite open cover of X. Suppose that \mathcal{U} is uncountable. We show that this assumption with lead to a contradiction. Thus \mathcal{U} must be countable.

By Theorem 1, there exists an open set V \subset X such that \mathcal{U} is not locally-countable at any point in V. For each positive integer n, let H_n be the following:

    H_n=\left\{x \in V: x \text{ is in at most } n \text{ sets in } \mathcal{U} \right\}

Note that V=\bigcup \limits_{j=1}^\infty H_j. Furthermore, each H_n is a closed set in the space V. Since X is a Baire space, every non-empty open subset of X is of second category (i.e. it cannot be a union of countably many closed and nowhere dense sets). Thus it cannot be that each H_n is nowhere dense in V. For some n, H_n is not nowhere dense. There must exist some open W \subset V such that H_n \cap W is dense in W. Because H_n is closed, W \subset H_n.

Choose y \in W. The point y is in at most n open sets in \mathcal{U}. Let U_1,U_2,\cdots,U_m \in \mathcal{U} such that y \in \bigcap \limits_{j=1}^m U_j. Clearly 1 \le m \le n. Let U=W \cap U_1 \cap \cdots \cap U_m. Note that y \in U \subset H_n \subset V.

Every point in U belongs to at most n many sets in \mathcal{U} and already belong to m sets in \mathcal{U}. So each point in U can belong to at most n-m additional open sets in \mathcal{U}. Consider the case n-m=0 and the case n-m>0. We show that each case leads to a contradiction.

Suppose that n-m=0. Then each point of U can only meet n open sets in \mathcal{U}, namely U_1,U_2,\cdots,U_m. This contradicts that \mathcal{U} is not locally-countable at points in U \subset V.

Suppose that k=n-m>0. Let \mathcal{U}^*=\mathcal{U}-\left\{U_1,\cdots,U_m \right\}. Let \mathcal{M} be the following collection:

    \mathcal{M}=\left\{U \cap \bigcap \limits_{O \in M} O \ne \varnothing: M \subset \mathcal{U}^* \text{ and } \lvert M \lvert=k \right\}

Each element of \mathcal{M} is an open subset of U that is the intersection of exactly n many open sets in \mathcal{U}. So \mathcal{M} is a collection of pairwise disjoint open sets. The open set U as a topological space has the CCC. So \mathcal{M} is at most countable. Thus the open set U meets at most countably many open sets in \mathcal{U}, contradicting that \mathcal{U} is not locally-countable at points in U \subset V.

Both cases n-m=0 and n-m>0 lead to contradiction. So \mathcal{U} must be countable. The proof to Theorem 3 is completed. \blacksquare

As a corollary to Theorem 3, we have the result that every Baire CCC metacompact space is Lindelof.

____________________________________________________________________

Some Applications of Theorems 2 and 3

In proving paracompactness in some of the theorems, we need a theorem involving the concept of star-countable open cover. A collection \mathcal{A} of subsets of a space X is said to be star-finite (star-countable) if for each A \in \mathcal{A}, only finitely (countably) many sets in \mathcal{A} meets A, i.e., the following set

    \left\{B \in \mathcal{A}: B \cap A \ne \varnothing \right\}

is finite (countable). The proof of the following theorem can be found in Engleking (see the direction (iv) implies (i) in the proof of Theorem 5.3.10 on page 326 in [1]).

    Theorem 4

      If every open cover of a regular space X has a star-countable open refinement, then X is paracompact.

As indicated in the above section, Theorem 2 and Theorem 3 have some obvious applications. We have the following theorems.

    Theorem 5

      Let X be a CCC space. Then X is paracompact if and only of X is Lindelof.

Proof of Theorem 5
The direction \Longleftarrow follows from the fact that any regular Lindelof space is paracompact.

The direction \Longrightarrow follows from Theorem 2. \blacksquare

    Theorem 6

      Every CCC para-Lindelof space is Lindelof.

Proof of Theorem 6
This also follows from Theorem 2. \blacksquare

    Theorem 7

      Every Baire CCC metacompact space is Lindelof.

Proof of Theorem 7
Let X be a Baire CCC metacompact space. Let \mathcal{U} be an open cover of X. By metacompactness, let \mathcal{V} be a point-finite open refinement of \mathcal{U}. By Theorem 3, \mathcal{V} must be countable. \blacksquare

    Theorem 8

      Every Baire CCC hereditarily metacompact space is hereditarily Lindelof.

Proof of Theorem 8
Let X be a Baire CCC hereditarily metacompact space. To show that X is hereditarily Lindelof, it suffices to show that every non-empty open subset is Lindelof. Let Y \subset X be open. Then Y has the CCC and is also metacompact. Being a Baire space is hereditary with respect to open subspaces. So Y is a Baire space too. By Theorem 7, Y is Lindelof. \blacksquare

    Theorem 9

      Every locally CCC regular para-Lindelof space is paracompact.

Proof of Theorem 9
A space is locally CCC if every point has an open neighborhood that has the CCC. Let X be a regular space that is locally CCC and para-Lindelof. Let \mathcal{U} be an open cover of X. Using the locally CCC assumption and by taking a refinement of \mathcal{U} if necessary, we can assume that each open set in \mathcal{U} has the CCC. By the para-Lindelof assumption, let \mathcal{V} be a locally-countable open refinement of \mathcal{U}. So each open set in \mathcal{V} has the CCC too.

Now we show that \mathcal{V} is star-countable. Let V \in \mathcal{V}. Let \mathcal{G} be the following collection:

    \mathcal{G}=\left\{V \cap W: W \in \mathcal{V} \right\}

which is is open cover of V. Within the subspace V, \mathcal{G} is a locally-countable open cover. By Theorem 2, \mathcal{G} must be countable. The collection \mathcal{G} represents all the open sets in \mathcal{V} that have non-empty intersection with V. Thus only countably many open sets in \mathcal{V} can meet V. So \mathcal{V} is a star-countable open refinement of \mathcal{U}. By Theorem 4, X is paracompact. \blacksquare

    Theorem 10

      Every locally CCC regular metacompact Baire space is paracompact.

Proof of Theorem 10
Let X be a regular space that is locally CCC and is a metacompact Baire space. Let \mathcal{U} be an open cover of X. Using the locally CCC assumption and by taking a refinement of \mathcal{U} if necessary, we can assume that each open set in \mathcal{U} has the CCC. By the metacompact assumption, let \mathcal{V} be a point-finite open refinement of \mathcal{U}. So each open set in \mathcal{V} has the CCC too. Each open set in \mathcal{V} is also a Baire space.

Now we show that \mathcal{V} is star-countable. Let V \in \mathcal{V}. Let \mathcal{G} be the following collection:

    \mathcal{G}=\left\{V \cap W: W \in \mathcal{V} \right\}

which is is open cover of V. Within the subspace V, \mathcal{G} is a point-finite open cover. By Theorem 3, \mathcal{G} must be countable. The collection \mathcal{G} represents all the open sets in \mathcal{V} that have non-empty intersection with V. Thus only countably many open sets in \mathcal{V} can meet V. So \mathcal{V} is a star-countable open refinement of \mathcal{U}. By Theorem 4, X is paracompact. \blacksquare

    Theorem 11

      Every locally compact metacompact perfectly normal space is paracompact.

Proof of Theorem 11
This follows from Theorem 10 after we prove the following two points:

  • Any locally compact space is a Baire space.
  • Any perfect locally compact space is locally CCC.

To see the first point, let Y be a locally compact space. Let W_1,W_2,W_3,\cdots be dense open sets in Y. Let y \in Y and let W \subset Y be open such that y \in W and \overline{W} is compact. We show that W contains a point that belongs to all W_n. Let X_1=W \cap W_1, which is open and non-empty. Next choose non-empty open X_2 such that \overline{X_2} \subset X_1 and X_2 \subset W_2. Next choose non-empty open X_3 such that \overline{X_3} \subset X_2 and X_3 \subset W_3. Continue in this manner, we have a sequence of open sets X_1,X_2,X_3,\cdots such that for each n, \overline{X_{n+1}} \subset X_n and \overline{X_n} is compact. The intersection of all the X_n is non-empty. The points in the intersection must belong to each W_n.

To see the second point, let Y be a locally compact space such that every closed set is a G_\delta-set. Suppose that Y is not locally CCC at y \in Y. Let U \subset Y be open such that y \in U and \overline{U} is compact. Then U must not have the CCC. Let \left\{U_\alpha: \alpha<\omega_1 \right\} be a pairwise disjoint collection of open subsets of U. Let O=\bigcup \limits_{\alpha<\omega_1} U_\alpha and let C=Y-O.

Let C=\bigcap \limits_{n=1}^\infty V_n where each V_n is open in Y and V_{n+1} \subset V_n for each integer n. For each \alpha<\omega_1, pick y_\alpha \in U_\alpha. For each y_\alpha, there is some integer f(\alpha) such that y_\alpha \notin V_{f(\alpha)}. So there must exist some integer n such that A=\left\{y_\alpha: f(\alpha)=n \right\} is uncountable.

The set A is an infinite subset of the compact set \overline{U}. So A has a limit point, say p (also called cluster point). Clearly p \notin O. So p \in C. In particular, p \in V_n. Then V_n contains some points of A. But for any y_\alpha \in A, y_\alpha \notin V_n=V_{f(\alpha)}, a contradiction. So Y must be locally CCC at each y \in Y. \blacksquare

____________________________________________________________________

Some Examples

Example 1
A CCC space X with an uncountable point-finite open covers. This example demonstrates that in Theorem 2, locally-finite or locally-countable cannot be replaced by point-finite. Consider the following product space:

    Y=\prod \limits_{\alpha < \omega_1} \left\{0,1 \right\}=\left\{0,1 \right\}^{\omega_1}

i.e, the product space of \omega_1 many copies of the two-point discrete space \left\{0,1 \right\}. Let X be the set of all points h \in Y such that h(\alpha)=1 for only finitely many \alpha<\omega_1.

The product space Y is the product of separable spaces, hence has the CCC. The space X is dense in Y. Hence X has the CCC. For each \alpha<\omega_1, define U_\alpha as follows:

    U_\alpha=\left\{h \in X: h(\alpha)=1 \right\}

Then \left\{U_\alpha:\alpha<\omega_1  \right\} is a point-finite open cover of X. Of course, X in this example is not a Baire space. \blacksquare

The following three examples center around the four properties in Theorem 7 (Baire + CCC + metacompact imply Lindelof). These examples show that each property in the hypothesis is crucial.

Example 2
A separable non-Lindelof space that is a Baire space. This example shows that the metacompact assumption is crucial for Theorem 7.

The example is the Sorgenfrey plane S \times S where S is the real line with the Sorgenfrey topology (generated by the half-open intervals of the form [a,b)). It is well known that S \times S is not Lindelof. The Sorgenfrey plane is Baire and is separable (hence CCC). Furthermore, S \times S is not metacompact (if it were, it would be Lindelof by Theorem 7). \blacksquare

Example 3
A non-Lindelof metacompact Baire space M. This example shows that the CCC assumption in Theorem 7 is necessary.

This space M is the subspace of Bing’s Example G that has finite support (defined and discussed in the post A subspace of Bing’s example G. It is normal and not collectionwise normal (hence cannot be Lindelof) and metacompact. The space M does not have CCC since it has uncountably many isolated points. Any space with a dense set of isolated points is a Baire space. Thus the space M is also a Baire space. \blacksquare

Example 4
A non-Lindelof CCC metacompact non-Baire space W. This example shows that the Baire space assumption in Theorem 7 is necessary.

Let W be the set of all non-empty finite subsets of the real line with the Pixley-Roy topology. Note that W is non-Lindelof and has the CCC and is metacompact. Of course it is not Baire. For more information on Pixley-Roy spaces, see the post called Pixley-Roy hyperspaces. For the purpose of this example, the Pixley-Roy space can be built on any uncountable separable metrizable space.

____________________________________________________________________

Reference

  1. Engelking, R., General Topology, Revised and Completed edition, Heldermann Verlag, Berlin, 1989.
  2. Tall, F. D., The Countable Chain Condition Versus Separability – Applications of Martin’s Axiom, Gen. Top. Appl., 4, 315-339, 1974.

____________________________________________________________________

\copyright \ 2014 \text{ by Dan Ma}

One way to find collectionwise normal spaces

Collectionwise normality is a property that is weaker than paracompactness and stronger than normality (see the implications below). Normal spaces need not be collectionwise normal. Bing’s Example G is an example of a normal and not collectionwise normal space (see the blog post “Bing’s Example G”). We discuss one instance when normal spaces are collectionwise normal, giving a way to obtain collectionwise normal spaces that are not paracompact.

    \text{ }
    \text{paracompact} \Longrightarrow \text{collectionwise normal} \Longrightarrow \text{normal}

___________________________________________________________________________________

Collectionwise Normal Spaces

A normal space is one in which any two disjoint closed sets can be separated by disjoint open sets. By induction, in a normal space any finite number of disjoint closed sets can be separated by disjoint open sets. Of course, the inductive reasoning cannot be carried over to the case of infinitely many disjoint closed sets. In the real line with the usual topology, the singleton sets \left\{x \right\}, where x is rational, are disjoint closed sets that cannot be simultaneously separated by disjoint open sets. In order to separate an infinite collection of disjoint closed sets, it makes sense to restrict on the type of collections of closed sets. A space X is collectionwise normal if every discrete collection of closed subsets of X can be separated by pairwise disjoint open subsets of X. The following is a more specific definition.

    Definition
    A space X is collectionwise normal if for every discrete collection \mathcal{A} of closed subsets of X, there exists a pairwise disjoint collection \mathcal{U}=\left\{U_A: A \in \mathcal{A} \right\} of open subsets of X such that A \subset U_A for each A \in \mathcal{A}.

For more details about the definitions of collectionwise normality, see “Definitions of Collectionwise Normal Spaces”. The implications displayed above are repeated below. None of the arrows is reversible.

    \text{ }
    \text{paracompact} \Longrightarrow \text{collectionwise normal} \Longrightarrow \text{normal}

As indicated above, Bing’s Example G is an example of a normal and not collectionwise normal space (see the blog post “Bing’s Example G”). The propositions in the next section can be used to obtain collectionwise normal spaces that are not paracompact.

___________________________________________________________________________________

When Normal implies Collectionwise Normal

Being able to simultaneously separate any discrete collection of closed sets is stronger than the property of merely being able to separate finite collection of disjoint closed sets. It turns out that the stronger property of collectionwise normality is required only for separating uncountable discrete collections of closed sets. As the following lemma shows, normality is sufficient to separate any countable discrete collection of closed sets.

Lemma 1
Let X be a normal space. Then for every discrete collection \left\{C_1,C_2,C_3,\cdots \right\} of closed subsets of X, there exists a pairwise disjoint collection \left\{O_1,O_2,O_3,\cdots \right\} of open subsets of X such that C_i \subset O_i for each i.

Proof of Lemma 1
Let \left\{C_1,C_2,C_3,\cdots \right\} be a discrete collection of closed subsets of X. For each i, choose disjoint open sets U_i and V_i such that C_i \subset U_i and \cup \left\{C_j: j \ne i \right\} \subset V_i. Let O_1=U_1. For each i>1, let O_i=U_i \cap V_1 \cap \cdots \cap V_{i-1}. It follows that O_i \cap O_j = \varnothing for all i \ne j. It is also clear that for each i, C_i \subset O_i. \blacksquare

We have the following propositions.

Proposition 2
Let X be a normal space. If all discrete collections of closed subsets of X are at most countable, then X is collectionwise normal.

Proposition 3
Let X be a normal space. If all closed and discrete subsets of X are at most countable (such a space is said to have countable extent), then X is collectionwise normal.

Proposition 4
Any normal and countably compact space is collectionwise normal.

Proposition 2 follows from Lemma 1. As noted in Proposition 3, any space in which all closed and discrete subsets are countable is said to have countable extent. It is easy to verify that X has countable extent if and only if all discrete collections of closed subsets of X are at most countable. If X is a countably compact space, then every infinite subset of X has a limit point. Thus Proposition 4 follows from the fact that any countably compact space has countable extent.

___________________________________________________________________________________

Paracompact Spaces

One way to find a collectionwise normal space that is not paracompact is to find a non-paracompact space that satisfies Propositions 3, 4 or 5. For example, \omega_1, the space of all countable ordinals with the order topology, is not paracompact. Since \omega_1 is normal and countably compact, it is collectionwise normal by Proposition 4. For a basic discussion of \omega_1 as a topological space, see “The First Uncountable Ordinal”.

As the following theorem shows, paracompact spaces are collectionwise normal. Thus the class of collectionwise normal spaces includes all metric spaces and paracompact spaces.

Theorem 5
If a space X is paracompact, then X is collectionwise normal.

Proof of Theorem 5
Let X be a paracompact space. Let \mathcal{A} be a discrete collection of closed subsets of X. For each x \in X, let O_x be open such that x \in O_x and O_x meets at most one element of \mathcal{A}. Let \mathcal{O}=\left\{O_x: x \in X \right\}. By the paracompactness of X, \mathcal{O} has a locally finite open refinement \mathcal{V}.

For each A \in \mathcal{A}, let W_A=\cup \left\{\overline{V}: V \in \mathcal{V} \text{ and } \overline{V} \cap A=\varnothing \right\} and let U_A=X-W_A. Each W_A is a closed set since \mathcal{V} is locally finite. Thus each U_A is open. Furthermore, for each A \in \mathcal{A}, A \subset U_A. It is easily checked that \left\{U_A: A \in \mathcal{A} \right\} is pairwise disjoint. \blacksquare

___________________________________________________________________________________

Reference

  1. Bing, R. H., Metrization of Topological Spaces, Canad. J. Math., 3, 175-186, 1951.
  2. Engelking, R., General Topology, Revised and Completed edition, Heldermann Verlag, Berlin, 1989.
  3. Willard, S., General Topology, Addison-Wesley Publishing Company, 1970.

___________________________________________________________________________________

\copyright \ \ 2012
Revised June 16, 2019

A subspace of Bing’s example G

Bing’s Example G is the first example of a topological space that is normal but not collectionwise normal (see [1]). Example G was an influential example from an influential paper. The Example G and its subspaces had been extensively studied. In addition to being normal and not collectionwise normal, Example G is not perfectly normal and not metacompact. See the previous post “Bing’s Example G” for a basic discussion of Example G. In this post we focus on one subspace of Example G examined by Michael in [3]. This subspace is normal, not collectionwise normal and not perfectly normal just like Example G. However it is metacompact. In [3], Michael proved that any metacompact collectionwise normal space is paracompact (metacompact was called pointwise paracompact in that paper). This subspace of Example G demonstrates that collectionwise normality in Michael’s theorem cannot be replaced by normality.

___________________________________________________________________________________

Bing’s Example G

For a more detailed discussion of Bing’s Example G in this blog, see the blog post “Bing’s Example G”. For the sake of completeness, we repeat the definition of Example G. Let P be any uncountable set. Let Q be the set of all subsets of P. Let F=2^Q be the set of all functions f: Q \rightarrow 2=\left\{0,1 \right\}. Obviously 2^Q is simply the Cartesian product of \lvert Q \lvert many copies of the two-point discrete space \left\{0,1 \right\}, i.e., \prod \limits_{q \in Q} \left\{0,1 \right\}. For each p \in P, define the function f_p: Q \rightarrow 2 by the following:

    \forall q \in Q, f_p(q)=1 if p \in q and f_p(q)=0 if p \notin q

Let F_P=\left\{f_p: p \in P \right\}. Let \tau be the set of all open subsets of 2^Q in the product topology. The following is another topology on 2^Q:

    \tau^*=\left\{U \cup V: U \in \tau \text{ and } V \subset 2^Q \text{ with } V \cap F_P=\varnothing \right\}

Bing’s Example G is the set F=2^Q with the topology \tau^*. In other words, each x \in F-F_P is made an isolated point and points in F_P retain the usual product open sets.

___________________________________________________________________________________

Michael’s Subspace of Example G

For each f \in F, let supp(f) be the support of f, i.e., supp(f)=\left\{q \in Q:f(q) \ne 0 \right\}. Michael in [3] considered the following subspace of F.

    M=F_P \cup \left\{f \in F: supp(f) \text{ is finite} \right\}

Michael in [3] used the letter G to denote the space M. We choose another letter to distinguish it from Example G. The subspace M consists of all points f_p \in F_P and all other f \in F such that f(q)=1 for only finitely many q \in Q. The space M is normal and not collectionwise Hausdorff (hence not collectionwise normal and not paracompact). By eliminating points f \in F that have values of 1 for infinitely many q \in Q, we obtain a subspace that is metacompact. We discuss the following points:

  • The space M is normal.
  • The space M is not collectionwise Hausdorff and hence not collectionwise normal.
  • The space M is metacompact.
  • The space M is not perfectly normal.

The space M is normal since the space F that is Example G is hereditarily normal (see the section called Bing’s Example G is Completely Normal in the post “Bing’s Example G”).

To show that the space M is not collectionwise Hausdorff, it is helpful to first look at M as a subspace of the product space 2^Q. The product space 2^Q has the countable chain condition (CCC) since it is a product of separable spaces. Note that M is dense in the product space 2^Q. Thus M as a subspace of the product space has the CCC.

In the space M, the set F_P is still a closed and discrete set. In the space M, open sets containing points of F_P are the same as product open sets in 2^Q relative to the set M. Since M has CCC (as a subspace of the product space 2^Q), M cannot have uncountably many pairwise disjoint open sets containing points of F_P (in either the product topology or the Example G subspace topology). It follows that M is not collectionwise Hausdorff. If it were, there would be uncountably many pairwise disjoint product open sets separating points in F_P, which is not possible.

To see that M is metacompact, let \mathcal{U} be an open cover of M. For each p \in P, choose U_p \in \mathcal{U} such that f_p \in U_p. For each p \in P, let W_p=\left\{f \in M: f(\left\{p \right\})=1 \right\}. Let \mathcal{V} be the following:

    \mathcal{V}=\left\{U_p \cap W_p: p \in P \right\} \cup \left\{\left\{x \right\}: x \in M-F_P \right\}

Note that \mathcal{V} is a point-finite open refinement of \mathcal{U}. Each U_p \cap W_p contains only one point of F_P, namely f_p. On the other hand, each f \in M with finite support can belong to at most finitely many U_p \cap W_p.

The space M is not perfectly normal. This point is alluded to in [3] by Michael and elsewhere in the literature, e.g. in Bing’s paper (see [1]) and in Engelking’s general topology text (see 5.53 on page 338 of [2]). In fact Michael indicated that one can obtain a perfectly normal example with the aforementioned properties using Example H defined in [1] instead of using the subspace M defined here in this post.

___________________________________________________________________________________

Reference

  1. Bing, R. H., Metrization of Topological Spaces, Canad. J. Math., 3, 175-186, 1951.
  2. Engelking, R., General Topology, Revised and Completed edition, Heldermann Verlag, Berlin, 1989.
  3. Michael, E., Point-finite and locally finite coverings, Canad. J. Math., 7, 275-279, 1955.
  4. Willard, S., General Topology, Addison-Wesley Publishing Company, 1970.

___________________________________________________________________________________

\copyright \ \ 2012

Cartesian Products of Two Paracompact Spaces – Continued

Consider the real line \mathbb{R} with a topology finer than the usual topology obtained by isolating each point in \mathbb{P} where \mathbb{P} is the set of all irrational numbers. The real line with this finer topology is called the Michael line and we use \mathbb{M} to denote this topological space. It is a classic result that \mathbb{M} \times \mathbb{P} is not normal (see “Michael Line Basics”). Even though the Michael line \mathbb{M} is paracompact (it is in fact hereditarily paracompact), \mathbb{M} is not perfectly normal. Result 3 below will imply that the Michael line cannot be perfectly normal. Otherwise \mathbb{M} \times \mathbb{P} would be paracompact (hence normal). Result 3 is the statement that if X is paracompact and perfectly normal and Y is a metric space then X \times Y is paracompact and perfectly normal. We also use this result to show that if X is hereditarily Lindelof and Y is a separable metric space, then X \times Y is hereditarily Lindelof (see Result 4 below).

This post is a continuation of the post “Cartesian Products of Two Paracompact Spaces”. In that post, four results are listed. They are:

Result 1

    If X is paracompact and Y is compact, then X \times Y is paracompact.

Result 2

    If X is paracompact and Y is \sigma-compact, then X \times Y is paracompact.

Result 3

    If X is paracompact and perfectly normal and Y is metrizable, then X \times Y is paracompact and perfectly normal.

Result 4

    If X is hereditarily Lindelof and Y is a separable metric space, then X \times Y is hereditarily Lindelof.

Result 1 and Result 2 are proved in the previous post “Cartesian Products of Two Paracompact Spaces”. Result 3 and Result 4 are proved in this post. All spaces are assumed to be regular.

___________________________________________________________________________________

Paracompact Spaces, Lindelof Spaces and Other Information

A paracompact space is one in which every open cover has a locally finite open refinement. The previous post “Cartesian Products of Two Paracompact Spaces” has a basic discussion on paracompact spaces. For the sake of completeness, we repeat here some of the results discussed in that post. A proof of Proposition 1 can be found in [1] (Theorem 5.1.11 in page 302) or in [2] (Theorem 20.7 in page 146).. For a proof of Proposition 2, see Theorem 3 in the previous post “Cartesian Products of Two Paracompact Spaces”. We provide a proof for Proposition 3.

Proposition 1
Let X be a regular space. Then X is paracompact if and only if every open cover \mathcal{U} of X has a \sigma-locally finite open refinement.

Proposition 2
Every F_\sigma-subset of a paracompact space is paracompact.

Proposition 3
Any paracompact space with a dense Lindelof subspace is Lindelof.

Proof of Proposition 3
Let L be a paracompact space. Let M \subset L be a dense Lindelof subspace. Let \mathcal{U} be an open cover of L. Since we are working with a regular space, let \mathcal{V} be an open cover of L such that \left\{\overline{V}: V \in \mathcal{V} \right\} refines \mathcal{U}. Let \mathcal{W} be a locally finite open refinement of \mathcal{V}. Choose \left\{W_1,W_2,W_3,\cdots \right\} \subset \mathcal{W} such that it is a cover of M. Since M \subset \bigcup \limits_{i=1}^\infty W_i, \overline{\bigcup \limits_{i=1}^\infty W_i}=L.

Since the sets W_i come from a locally finite collection, they are closure preserving. Hence we have:

    \overline{\bigcup \limits_{i=1}^\infty W_i}=\bigcup \limits_{i=1}^\infty \overline{W_i}=L

For each i, choose some U_i \in \mathcal{U} such that \overline{W_i} \subset U_i. Then \left\{U_1,U_2,U_3,\cdots \right\} is a countable subcollection of \mathcal{U} covering the space L. \blacksquare

A space is said to be a perfectly normal if it is a normal space with the additional property that every closed subset is a G_\delta-set in the space (equivalently every open subset is an F_\sigma-set). We need two basic results about hereditarily Lindelof spaces. A space is Lindelof if every open cover of that space has a countable subcover. A space is hereditarily Lindelof if every subspace of that space is Lindelof. Proposition 4 below, stated without proof, shows that to prove a space is hereditarily Lindelof, we only need to show that every open subspace is Lindelof.

Proposition 4
Let L be a space. Then L is hereditarily Lindelof if and only if every open subspace of L is Lindelof.

Proposition 5
Let L be a Lindelof space. Then L is hereditarily Lindelof if and only if L is perfectly normal.

Proof of Proposition 5
\Rightarrow Suppose L is hereditarily Lindelof. It is well known that regular Lindelof space is normal. Thus L is normal. It remains to show that every open subset of L is F_\sigma. Let U \subset L be an non-empty open set. For each x \in U, let V_x be open such that x \in V_x and \overline{V_x} \subset U (the space is assumed to be regular). By assumption, the open set U is Lindelof. The open sets V_x form an open cover of U. Thus U is the union of countably many \overline{V}_x.

\Leftarrow Suppose L is perfectly normal. To show that L is hereditarily Lindelof, it suffices to show that every open subset of L is Lindelof (by Proposition 4). Let U \subset L be non-empty open. By assumption, U=\bigcup \limits_{i=1}^\infty F_i where each F_i is a closed set in L. Since the Lindelof property is hereditary with respect to closed subsets, U is Lindelof. \blacksquare

Another important piece of information that we need is the following metrization theorem. It shows that being a metrizable space is equivalent to have a base that is \sigma-locally finite. In proving Result 3, we will assume that the metric factor has such a base. This is a classic metrization theorem (see [1] or [2] or any other standard topology text).

Theorem 6
Let X be a space. Then X is metrizable if and only if X has a \sigma-locally finite base.

___________________________________________________________________________________

Result 3

Result 3 is the statement that:

    If X is paracompact and perfectly normal and Y is a metric space then X \times Y is paracompact and perfectly normal.

Result 3 follows from the following two lemmas.

Lemma 7
If the following two conditions hold:

  • every open subset of X is an F_\sigma-set in X,
  • Y is a metric space,

then every open subset of X \times Y is an F_\sigma-set in X \times Y.

Proof of Lemma 7
Let U be a open subset of X \times Y. If U=\varnothing, then U is certainly the union of countably many closed sets. So assume U \ne \varnothing. Let \mathcal{B}=\bigcup \limits_{i=1}^\infty \mathcal{B}_i be a base for Y such that each \mathcal{B}_i is locally finite in Y (by Theorem 6, such a base exists since Y is metrizable).

Consider all non-empty B \in \mathcal{B} such that we can choose nonempty open set W_B \subset X with W_B \times \overline{B} \subset U. Since U is non-empty open, such pairs (B, W_B) exist. Let \mathcal{B}^* be the collection of all non-empty B \in \mathcal{B} for which there is a matching non-empty W_B. For each i, let \mathcal{B}_i^*=\mathcal{B}^* \cap \mathcal{B}_i. Of course, each \mathcal{B}_i^* is still locally finite.

Since every open subset of X is an F_\sigma-set in X, for each W_B, we can write W_B as

    W_B=\bigcup \limits_{j=1}^\infty W_{B,j}

where each W_{B,i} is closed in X.

For each i=1,2,3,\cdots and each j=1,2,3,\cdots, consider the following collection:

    \mathcal{V}_{i,j}=\left\{W_{B,j} \times \overline{B}: B \in \mathcal{B}_i^* \right\}

Each element of \mathcal{V}_{i,j} is a closed set in X \times Y. Since \mathcal{B}_i^* is a locally finite collection in Y, \mathcal{V}_{i,j} is a locally finite collection in X \times Y. Define V_{i,j}=\bigcup \mathcal{V}_{i,j}. The set V_{i,j} is a union of closed sets. In general, the union of closed sets needs not be closed. However, V_{i,j} is still a closed set in X \times Y since \mathcal{V}_{i,j} is a locally finite collection of closed sets. This is because a locally finite collection of sets is closure preserving. Note the following:

    \overline{V_{i,j}}=\overline{\bigcup \mathcal{V}_{i,j}}=\overline{\bigcup \left\{W_{B,j} \times \overline{B}: B \in \mathcal{B}_i^* \right\}}=\bigcup \left\{\overline{W_{B,j} \times \overline{B}}: B \in \mathcal{B}_i^* \right\}

      =\bigcup \left\{W_{B,j} \times \overline{B}: B \in \mathcal{B}_i^* \right\}=V_{i,j}

Finally, we have U=\bigcup \limits_{i=1}^\infty \bigcup \limits_{j=1}^\infty V_{i,j}, which is the union of countably many closed sets. \blacksquare

Lemma 8
If X is a paracompact space satisfying the following two conditions:

  • every open subset of X is an F_\sigma-set in X,
  • Y is a metric space,

then X \times Y is paracompact.

Proof of Lemma 8
As in the proof of the above lemma, let \mathcal{B}=\bigcup \limits_{i=1}^\infty \mathcal{B}_i be a base for Y such that each \mathcal{B}_i is locally finite in Y. Let \mathcal{U} be an open cover of X \times Y. Assume that elements of \mathcal{U} are of the form A \times B where A is open in X and B \in \mathcal{B}.

For each B \in \mathcal{B}, consider the following two items:

    \mathcal{W}_B=\left\{A: A \times B \in \mathcal{U} \right\}

    W_B=\bigcup \mathcal{W}_B

To simplify matter, we only consider B \in \mathcal{B} such that \mathcal{W}_B \ne \varnothing. Each W_B is open in X and hence by assumption an F_\sigma-set in X. Thus by Proposition 2, each W_B is paracompact. Note that \mathcal{W}_B is an open cover of W_B. Let \mathcal{H}_B be a locally finite open refinement of \mathcal{W}_B. Consider the following two items:

    For each j=1,2,3,\cdots, let \mathcal{V}_j=\left\{A \times B: A \in \mathcal{H}_B \text{ and } B \in \mathcal{B}_j \right\}

    \mathcal{V}=\bigcup \limits_{j=1}^\infty \mathcal{V}_j

We observe that \mathcal{V} is an open cover of X \times Y and that \mathcal{V} refines \mathcal{U}. Furthermore each \mathcal{V}_j is a locally finite collection. The open cover \mathcal{U} we start with has a \sigma-locally finite open refinement. Thus X \times Y is paracompact. \blacksquare

___________________________________________________________________________________

Result 4

Result 4 is the statement that:

    If X is hereditarily Lindelof and Y is a separable metric space, then X \times Y is hereditarily Lindelof.

Proof of Result 4
Suppose X is hereditarily Lindelof and that Y is a separable metric space. It is well known that regular Lindelof spaces are paracompact. Thus X is paracompact. By Proposition 5, X is perfectly normal. By Result 3, X \times Y is paracompact and perfectly normal.

Let D be a countable dense subset of Y. We can think of D as a \sigma-compact space. The product of any Lindelof space with a \sigma-compact space is Lindelof (see Corollary 3 in the post “The Tube Lemma”). Thus X \times D is Lindelof. Furthermore X \times D is a dense Lindelof subspace of X \times Y. By Proposition 3, X \times Y is Lindelof. By Proposition 5, X \times Y is hereditarily Lindelof. \blacksquare

Remark
In the previous post “Bernstein Sets and the Michael Line”, a non-normal product space where one factor is Lindelof and the other factor is a separable metric space is presented. That Lindelof space is not hereditarily Lindelof (it has uncountably many isolated points). Note that by Result 4, for any such non-normal product space, the Lindelof factor cannot be hereditarily Lindelof.

___________________________________________________________________________________

Reference

  1. Engelking, R., General Topology, Revised and Completed edition, Heldermann Verlag, Berlin, 1989.
  2. Willard, S., General Topology, Addison-Wesley Publishing Company, 1970.

___________________________________________________________________________________

\copyright \ \ 2012

Cartesian Products of Two Paracompact Spaces

In some previous posts we discuss examples surrounding the Michael line showing that the product of a paracompact space and a complete metric space needs not be normal (see “Michael Line Basics”) and that the product of a Lindelof space and a separable metric space need not be normal (see “Bernstein Sets and the Michael Line”). These examples are classic counterexamples demonstrating that both paracompactness and Lindelofness are not preserved by taking two-factor cartesian products even when one of the factors is nice (complete metric space in the first example and separable metric space in the second example). We now show some positive results. Of course, these results require additional conditions on one or both of the factors. We prove the following results.

Result 1

    If X is paracompact and Y is compact, then X \times Y is paracompact.

Result 2

    If X is paracompact and Y is \sigma-compact, then X \times Y is paracompact.

Result 3

    If X is paracompact and perfectly normal and Y is metrizable, then X \times Y is paracompact and perfectly normal.

Result 4

    If X is hereditarily Lindelof and Y is a separable metric space, then X \times Y is hereditarily Lindelof.

With Results 1 and 2, compact spaces and \sigma-compact spaces can be called productively paracompact since the product of each of these spaces with any paracompact space is paracompact. We prove Result 1 and Result 2 below.

Result 3 and Result 4 are proved in another post Cartesian Products of Two Paracompact Spaces – Continued.

___________________________________________________________________________________

Paracompact Spaces

First, recall some definitions. All spaces are at least regular (to us regular implies Hausdorff). Let X be a space. A collection \mathcal{A} of subsets of X is said to be a cover of X if X=\bigcup \mathcal{A} (in words every point of the space belongs to one set in the collection). Furthermore, \mathcal{A} is an open cover of X is it is a cover of X consisting of open subsets of X.

Let \mathcal{A} and \mathcal{B} be covers of the space X. The cover \mathcal{B} is said to be a refinement of \mathcal{A} (\mathcal{B} is said to refine \mathcal{A}) if for every B \in \mathcal{B}, there is some A \in \mathcal{A} such that B \subset A. The cover \mathcal{B} is said to be an open refinement of \mathcal{A} if \mathcal{B} refines \mathcal{A} and \mathcal{B} is an open cover.

A collection \mathcal{A} of subsets of X is said to be a locally finite collection if for each point x \in X, there is a non-empty open subset V of X such that x \in V and V has non-empty intersection with at most finitely many sets in \mathcal{A}. An open cover \mathcal{A} of X is said to have a locally finite open refinement if there exists an open cover \mathcal{C} of X such that \mathcal{C} refines \mathcal{A} and \mathcal{C} is a locally finite collection. We have the following definition.

Definition

    The space X is said to be paracompact if every open cover of X has a locally finite open refinement.

A collection \mathcal{U} of subsets of the space X is said to be a \sigma-locally finite collection if \mathcal{U}=\bigcup \limits_{i=1}^\infty \mathcal{U}_i such that each \mathcal{U}_i is a locally finite collection of subsets of X. Consider the property that every open cover of X has a \sigma-locally finite open refinement. This on the surface is a stronger property than paracompactness. However, Theorem 1 below shows that it is actually equivalent to paracompactness. The proof of Theorem 1 can be found in [1] (Theorem 5.1.11 in page 302) or in [2] (Theorem 20.7 in page 146).

Theorem 1
Let X be a regular space. Then X is paracompact if and only if every open cover \mathcal{U} of X has a \sigma-locally finite open refinement.

Theorem 2 below is another characterization of paracompactness that is useful. For a proof of Theorem 2, see “Finite and Countable Products of the Michael Line”.

Theorem 2
Let X be a regular space. Then X is paracompact if and only if the following holds:

    For each open cover \left\{U_t: t \in T \right\} of X, there exists a locally finite open cover \left\{V_t: t \in T \right\} such that \overline{V_t} \subset U_t for each t \in T.

Theorem 3 below shows that paracompactness is hereditary with respect to F_\sigma-subsets.

Theorem 3
Every F_\sigma-subset of a paracompact space is paracompact.

Proof of Theorem 3
Let X be paracompact. Let Y \subset X such that Y=\bigcup \limits_{i=1}^\infty Y_i where each Y_i is a closed subset of X. Let \mathcal{U} be an open cover of Y. For each U \in \mathcal{U}, let U^* be open in X such that U^* \cap Y=U.

For each i, let \mathcal{U}_i^* be the set of all U^* such that U \cap Y_i \ne \varnothing. Let \mathcal{V}_i^* be a locally finite refinement of \mathcal{U}_i^* \cup \left\{X-Y_i \right\}. Let \mathcal{V}_i be the following:

    \mathcal{V}_i=\left\{V \cap Y: V \in \mathcal{V}_i^* \text{ and } V \cap Y_i \ne \varnothing \right\}

It is clear that each \mathcal{V}_i is a locally finite collection of open set in Y covering Y_i. All the \mathcal{V}_i together form a refinement of \mathcal{U}. Thus \mathcal{V}=\bigcup \limits_{i=1}^\infty \mathcal{V}_i is a \sigma-locally finite open refinement of \mathcal{U}. By Theorem 1, the F_\sigma-set Y is paracompact. \blacksquare
___________________________________________________________________________________

Result 1

Result 1 is the statement that:

    If X is paracompact and Y is compact, then X \times Y is paracompact.

To prove Result 1, we use the Tube lemma (for a proof, see “The Tube Lemma”).

The Tube Lemma
Let X be any space and Y be compact. For each x \in X and for each open set U \subset X \times Y such that \left\{x \right\} \times Y \subset U, there is an open set O \subset X such that \left\{x \right\} \times Y \subset O \times Y \subset U.

Proof of Result 1
Let \mathcal{U} be an open cover of X \times Y. For each x \in X, choose a finite \mathcal{U}_x \subset \mathcal{U} such that \mathcal{U}_x is a cover of \left\{x \right\} \times Y. By the Tube Lemma, for each x \in X, there is an open set O_x \subset X such that \left\{x \right\} \times Y \subset O_x \times Y \subset \cup \mathcal{U}_x. Since X is paracompact, by Theorem 2, let \left\{W_x: x \in X \right\} be a locally finite open refinement of \left\{O_x: x \in X \right\} such that W_x \subset O_x for each x \in X.

Let \mathcal{W}=\left\{(W_x \times Y) \cap U: x \in X, U \in \mathcal{U}_x \right\}. We claim that \mathcal{W} is a locally finite open refinement of \mathcal{U}. First, this is an open cover of X \times Y. To see this, let (a,b) \in X \times Y. Then a \in W_x for some x \in X. Furthermore, a \in O_x and (a,b) \in \cup \mathcal{U}_x. Thus, (a,b) \in (W_x \times Y) \cap U for some U \in \mathcal{U}_x. Secondly, it is clear that \mathcal{W} is a refinement of the original cover \mathcal{U}.

It remains to show that \mathcal{W} is locally finite. To see this, let (a,b) \in X \times Y. Then there is an open V in X such that x \in V and V can meets only finitely many W_x. Then V \times Y can meet only finitely many sets in \mathcal{W}. \blacksquare

___________________________________________________________________________________

Result 2

Result 2 is the statement that:

    If X is paracompact and Y is \sigma-compact, then X \times Y is paracompact.

Proof of Result 2
Note that the \sigma-compact space Y is Lindelof. Since regular Lindelof are normal, Y is normal and is thus completely regular. So we can embed Y into a compact space K. For example, we can let K=\beta Y, which is the Stone-Cech compactification of Y (see “Embedding Completely Regular Spaces into a Cube”). For our purpose here, any compact space containing Y will do. By Result 1, X \times K is paracompact. Note that X \times Y can be regarded as a subspace of X \times K.

Let Y=\bigcup \limits_{i=1}^\infty Y_i where each Y_i is compact in Y. Note that X \times Y=\bigcup \limits_{i=1}^\infty X \times Y_i and each X \times Y_i is a closed subset of X \times K. Thus the product X \times Y is an F_\sigma-subset of X \times K. According to Theorem 3, F_\sigma-subsets of any paracompact space is paracompact space. Thus X \times Y is paracompact. \blacksquare

___________________________________________________________________________________

Reference

  1. Engelking, R., General Topology, Revised and Completed edition, Heldermann Verlag, Berlin, 1989.
  2. Willard, S., General Topology, Addison-Wesley Publishing Company, 1970.

___________________________________________________________________________________

\copyright \ \ 2012

Bernstein Sets and the Michael Line

Let \mathbb{M} be the Michael line and let \mathbb{P} be the set of all irrational numbers with the Euclidean topology. In the post called “Michael Line Basics”, we show that the product \mathbb{M} \times \mathbb{P} is not normal. This is a classic counterexample showing that the product of two paracompact spaces need not be normal even when one of the factors is a complete metric space. The Michael line \mathbb{M} is not Lindelof. A natural question is: can the first factor be made a Lindelof space? In this post, as an application of Bernstein sets, we present a non-normal product space where one factor is Lindelof and the other factor is a separable metric space. It is interesting to note that while one factor is upgraded (from paracompact to Lindelof), the other factor is downgraded (from a complete metric space to just a separable metric space).

Bernstein sets have been discussed previously in this blog. They are special subsets of the real line and with the Euclidean subspace topology, they are spaces in which the Banach-Mazur game is undecidable (see the post “Bernstein Sets Are Baire Spaces”). A Bernstein set is a subset B of the real line such that every uncountable closed subset of the real line has non-empty intersection with both B and the complement of B.

Bernstein sets are constructed by transfinite induction. The procedure starts by ordering all uncountable closed subsets of the real line in a sequence of length that is as long as the cardinality of continuum. To see how Bernstein sets are constructed, see the post “Bernstein Sets Are Baire Spaces”.

After we discuss a generalization of the definition of the Michael line, we discuss the non-normal product space based on Bernstein sets.
___________________________________________________________________________________

Generalizing the Michael Line

Let \mathbb{R} be the real number line. Let \mathbb{P} be the set of all irrational numbers and let \mathbb{Q}=\mathbb{R}-\mathbb{P}. Recall that the Michael line is the real line \mathbb{R} topologized by letting points in \mathbb{P} discrete and letting points in \mathbb{Q} retain their usual open neighborhoods. We can carry out the same process on any partition of the real number line.

Let D and E be disjoint sets such that \mathbb{R}=D \cup E where the set E is dense in the real line. The intention is to make D the discrete part and E the Euclidean part. In other words, we topologize \mathbb{R} be letting points in D discrete and letting points in E retain their Euclidean open sets. Let X_D denote the resulting topological space. For the lack of a better term, we call the space X_D the modified Michael line. An open set in the space X_D is of the form U \cup V where U is a Euclidean open subset of the real line and V \subset D. We have the following result:

    Proposition
    Suppose that D is not an F_\sigma-set in the Euclidean real line and that D is dense in the Euclidean real line. Then the product space X_D \times D is not normal (the second factor D is considered a subspace of the Euclidean real line).

In the post “Michael Line Basics”, we give a proof that \mathbb{M} \times \mathbb{P} is not normal. This proof hinges on the same two facts about the set D in the hypothesis in the above proposition. Thus the proof for the above proposition is just like the one for \mathbb{M} \times \mathbb{P}. Whenever we topologize the modified Michael line by using a non-F_\sigma-set as the discrete part, we can always be certain that we have a non-normal product as indicated here.

___________________________________________________________________________________

Non-Normal Product Space

Let B be any Bernstein set. The set B is clearly not an F_\sigma-set in the real line and is clearly dense in the real line. Then X_B \times B is not normal. Note that in X_B, the set B is discrete and its complement \mathbb{R}-B has the usual topology. To see that X_B is Lindelof, note that any open cover of X_B has a countable subcollection that covers \mathbb{R}-B. This countable subcollection consists of Euclidean open sets. Furthermore, the complement of the union of these countably many Euclidean open sets must contain all but countably many points of the Bernstein set B (otherwise there would be an uncountable Euclidean closed set that misses B).

As commented at the beginning, in obtaining this non-normal product space, one factor is enhanced at the expense of the other factor (one is made Lindelof while the other is no longer a complete metric space). Even though any Bernstein set (with the Euclidean topology) is a separable metric space, it cannot be completely metrizable. Any completely metrizable subset of the real line must be a G_\delta-set in the real line. Furthermore any uncountable G_\delta subset of the real line must contain a Cantor set and thus cannot be a Bernstein set.

A similar example to X_B \times B is presented in E. Michael’s paper (see [3]). It is hinted in footnote 4 of that paper that with the additional assumption of continuum hypothesis (CH), one can have a non-normal product space where one factor is a Lindelof space and the second factor is the space of irrationals. So with an additional set-theoretic assumption, we can keep one factor from losing complete metrizability. For this construction, see point (d) in Example 3.2 of [2].

___________________________________________________________________________________

A Brief Remark

Note that the Lindelof space X_B presented here is not hereditarily Lindelof, since it has uncountably many isolated points. Can a hereditarily Lindelof example be constructed such that its product with a particular separable metric space is not normal? The answer is no. The product of a hereditarily Lindelof space and any separable metric space is hereditarily Lindelof (see Result 4 in the post Cartesian Products of Two Paracompact Spaces – Continued).

___________________________________________________________________________________

Reference

  1. Engelking, R., General Topology, Revised and Completed edition, Heldermann Verlag, Berlin, 1989.
  2. Michael, E., Paracompactness and the Lindelof property in Finite and Countable Cartesian Products, Compositio Math. 23 (1971) 199-214.
  3. Michael, E., The product of a normal space and a metric space need not be normal, Bull. Amer. Math. Soc., 69 (1963) 375-376.
  4. Willard, S., General Topology, Addison-Wesley Publishing Company, 1970.

___________________________________________________________________________________

\copyright \ \ 2012

Finite and Countable Products of the Michael Line

Consider the real number line \mathbb{R} with a topology stronger than the Euclidean topology such that the irrational numbers are isolated and the rational numbers retain their Euclidean open neighborhoods. When the real number line is endowed with this topology, the resulting topological space is called the Michael line and is denoted by \mathbb{M}. It is well known that \mathbb{M} \times \mathbb{P} is not normal where \mathbb{P} is the space of irrational numbers with the Euclidean topology. This and other basic results about the Michael line are discussed in the post Michael Line Basics. In this post, we show that \mathbb{M}^n is paracompact for any positive integer n and that \mathbb{M}^\omega (the product of countably and infinitely many copies of \mathbb{M}) is not normal. Thus the Michael line is an example demonstrating that even when paracompactness is preserved by taking finite products, it can be destroyed by taking infinite product.

The results discussed in this post are from a paper by E. Michael (Example 1.1 in [2]). This paper had been discussed previously in this blog (see Two footnotes in a paper of E. Michael).

As discussed before, let \mathbb{R} be the real number line. Let \mathbb{P} be the set of all irrational numbers. Let \mathbb{Q}=\mathbb{R}-\mathbb{P}, the set of all rational numbers. Let \tau be the usual topology of the real line \mathbb{R}. The following is a base that defines the topology for the Michael line \mathbb{M}.

    \mathcal{B}=\tau \cup \left\{\left\{ x \right\}: x \in \mathbb{P}\right\}

Other basic results about the Michael line are discussed in Michael Line Basics.

___________________________________________________________________________________

Paracompactness

A space X is paracompact if every open cover of X has a locally finite open refinement. In proving \mathbb{M}^n is paracompact, we need two basic results about paracompactness. The proof of Theorem 1 can be found in [1] (Theorem 5.1.11 in page 302) or in [3] (Theorem 20.7 in page 146). We prove Theorem 2.

Theorem 1
Let X be a regular space. Then X is paracompact if and only if every open cover of X has an open \sigma-locally finite refinement, i.e., the following holds:

    every open cover \mathcal{U} of X has an open refinement \bigcup \limits_{j=1}^\infty \mathcal{V}_j such that each \mathcal{V}_j is a locally finite collection of open subsets of X.

Theorem 2
Let X be a regular space. Then X is paracompact if and only if the following hold:

    For each open cover \left\{U_t: t \in T \right\} of X, there exists a locally finite open cover \left\{V_t: t \in T \right\} such that \overline{V_t} \subset U_t for each t \in T.

Proof of Theorem 2
The direction \Longleftarrow is clear.

\Longrightarrow Let X be paracompact. Let \mathcal{U}=\left\{U_t: t \in T \right\} be an open cover of X. By regularity, there is an open cover \mathcal{W} of X such that \left\{\overline{W}: W \in \mathcal{W} \right\} refines \mathcal{U}. Since X is paracompact, \mathcal{W} has an open locally finite refinement \mathcal{H}=\left\{H_a: a \in A \right\}.

We now tie \mathcal{H} to the original open cover \mathcal{U}. For each a \in A, choose f(a) \in T such that \overline{H_a} \subset U_{f(a)}. Now, we go the opposite direction, i.e., for each t \in T, consider all a \in A such that \overline{H_a} \subset U_{f(a)}=U_t. For each t \in T, let V_t be defined by:

    V_t=\bigcup \left\{H_a: a \in A \text { and } \overline{H_a} \subset U_{f(a)}=U_t \right\}=\bigcup \limits_{f(a)=t} H_a

Each V_t is open since it is a union of open sets. Since \mathcal{H} is locally finite, any subcollection of \mathcal{H} is closure preserving. We have:

    \overline{V_t}=\bigcup \left\{\overline{H_a}: a \in A \text { and } \overline{H_a} \subset U_{f(a)}=U_t \right\}=\bigcup \limits_{f(a)=t} \overline{H_a}

Thus we have \overline{V_t} \subset U_t for all t \in T. Since \mathcal{H} is locally finite, \left\{V_t: t \in T \right\} is locally finite. Furthermore, \left\{V_t: t \in T \right\} is clearly a cover of X. Thus Theorem 2 is established. \blacksquare

___________________________________________________________________________________

Finite Products

What makes the Michael line finitely productive for paracompactness is that all but countably many points in \mathbb{M} are isolated. The paracompactness of the finite products of the Michael line follows from Theorem 4 (see Corollary 5 below). Lemma 3 is used in proving Theorem 4.

Lemma 3
Let X be a space such that all but countably many points of X are isolated. Let A be the set of all isolated points of X. Then for each n=2,3,4,\cdots, X-A^n can be expressed as the following:

    X-A^n=\bigcup \limits_{k=1}^\infty Y_k satisfying the following:

    • For each k, Y_k is homeomorphic to X^{n-1}.
    • For each k, there exists a continuous map F_k:X^n \rightarrow Y_k such that F_k \upharpoonright Y_k is the indentity map.

Proof of Lemma 3
Note that X-A is countable. Fix n \in \left\{2,3,4,\cdots \right\}. For each x \in X^n, express x=(x_1,x_2,\cdots,x_n). For each i<n and for each a \in X-A, let Y_{i,a}=\left\{x \in X^n: x_i=a \right\} (the i^{th} coordinate is fixed and the other n-1 coordinates are free to vary). There are only countably many such Y_{i,a}. Clearly X-A^n is the union of all Y_{i,a}. Furthermore, each Y_{i,a} is homeomorphic to X^{n-1}.

Define F_{i,a}:X^n \rightarrow Y_{i,a} by mapping each (x_1,x_2,\cdots,x_i,\cdots,x_n) to (x_1,x_2,\cdots,a,\cdots,x_n). In other words, the i^{th} coordinate of each point is mapped to the fixed point a. This is a continuous map since it is a projection map. It is clear that when this map is restricted to Y_{i,a}, it is the identity map.

When we order all Y_{i,a} in a sequence Y_1,Y_2,Y_3,\cdots, the lemma is established. \blacksquare

Theorem 4
Let X be a regular space such that all but countably many points of X are isolated. Then X^n is paracompact for each n=1,2,3,\cdots.

Proof of Theorem 4
We prove X^n is paracompact by induction on n. Let A be the set of all isolated points of X. Let B=X-A.

First we show X is paracompact. Let \mathcal{U} be an open cover of X. Enumerate B by \left\{b_1,b_2,b_3,\cdots \right\}. For each i, choose U_i \in \mathcal{U} with b_i \in U_i. Let \mathcal{U}_i=\left\{U_i \right\}. Let \mathcal{A} be the set of all \left\{ x \right\} where x \notin \bigcup \limits_{i=1}^\infty U_i. Then \mathcal{A} \cup \mathcal{U}_1 \cup \mathcal{U}_2 \cup \mathcal{U}_3 \cup \cdots is an open \sigma-locally finite refinement of \mathcal{U}. By Theorem 1, X is paracompact.

Suppose that X^{n-1} is paracompact where n \ge 2. Let \mathcal{U}=\left\{U_t: t \in T \right\} be an open cover of X^n. By Lemma 3, there exist Y_1,Y_2,Y_3,\cdots, all subspaces of X^n, such that:

    X-A^n=\bigcup \limits_{k=1}^\infty Y_k satisfying the following:

    • For each k, Y_k is homeomorphic to X^{n-1}.
    • For each k, there exists a continuous map F_k:X^n \rightarrow Y_k such that F_k \upharpoonright Y_k is the indentity map.

Fix k where k=1,2,3,\cdots. Note that \left\{U_t \cap Y_k: t \in T \right\} is an open cover of Y_k. Since each Y_k is paracompact, using Theorem 2, we can find a locally finite open refinement \left\{V_t: t \in T \right\} (open in Y_k) of \left\{U_t \cap Y_k: t \in T \right\} such that V_t \subset U_t \cap Y_k for each t \in T. For each t, let W_{k,t}=F_k^{-1}(V_t) \cap U_t.

Then \left\{W_{k,t}: t \in T \right\} is a locally finite collection of open subsets of X^n covering Y_k. Since the map F_k is identity on Y_k, V_t \subset F_k^{-1}(V_t). Thus \left\{W_{k,t}: t \in T \right\} is a cover of Y_k. To see that it is locally finite, let z \in X^n. We have F_k(z) \in Y_k. There exists V (open in Y_k) such that F_k(z) \in V and V only meets finitely many V_t, say, V_{t_1},V_{t_2},\cdots,V_{t_m}. Consider the following the open sets:

    W_{k,t_1}=F_k^{-1}(V_{t_1}) \cap U_{t_1}
    W_{k,t_2}=F_k^{-1}(V_{t_2}) \cap U_{t_2}

      \cdot
      \cdot
      \cdot

    W_{k,t_m}=F_k^{-1}(V_{t_m}) \cap U_{t_m}

F_k^{-1}(V) is an open set containing z. It follows that the open sets W_{k,t} that F_k^{-1}(V) can meet are limited to ones listed above. For any s \in T where s \notin \left\{t_1,t_2,\cdots,t_m \right\}, V_s \cap V=\varnothing. Thus F_k^{-1}(V) \cap F_k^{-1}(V_s)=\varnothing and F_k^{-1}(V) \cap W_s=\varnothing. Thus \left\{W_{k,t}: t \in T \right\} is locally finite in X^n.

For each k=1,2,3,\cdots, let \mathcal{W}_k be \left\{W_{k,t}: t \in T \right\}, which is an open locally finite collection covering Y_k (as shown above). All together \bigcup \limits_{k=1}^\infty \mathcal{W}_k is an open \sigma-locally finite collection covering X^n-A^n. Let \mathcal{A} be the set of all \left\{ x \right\} where x \in A^n. Then \mathcal{A} \cup \bigcup \limits_{k=1}^\infty \mathcal{W}_k is an open \sigma-locally finite refinement of \mathcal{U}. By Theorem 1, X^n is paracompact. \blacksquare

Corollary 5
For each n=1,2,3,\cdots, \mathbb{M}^n is paracompact.

___________________________________________________________________________________

Infinite Products

Let \mathbb{P} be the space of the irrational numbers with the Euclidean topology. Let \omega be the set of all nonnegative integers. We now show that \mathbb{M}^\omega, the product of countably and infinitely many copies of the Michael line, is not normal. Before doing that, we point out that when \omega is considered a discrete space, \omega^\omega, the product of countably and infinitely many copies of \omega, is homeomorphic to \mathbb{P} (Thinking about the Space of Irrationals Topologically).

Let D be a countably infinite subset of the Michael line \mathbb{M} such that D is closed and discrete. As discussed above, D^\omega is a homeomorphic copy of \mathbb{P}. Furthermore D^\omega is a closed subset of \mathbb{M}^\omega. Thus \mathbb{M} \times \mathbb{M}^\omega contains \mathbb{M} \times D^\omega \cong \mathbb{M} \times \mathbb{P} as a closed subspace. Since \mathbb{M} \times \mathbb{P} is not normal, \mathbb{M} \times \mathbb{M}^\omega is not normal. On the other hand, \mathbb{M}^\omega is homeomorphic to \mathbb{M} \times \mathbb{M}^\omega. Thus \mathbb{M}^\omega is not normal. \blacksquare

___________________________________________________________________________________

Reference

  1. Engelking, R., General Topology, Revised and Completed edition, 1989, Heldermann Verlag, Berlin.
  2. Michael, E., Paracompactness and the Lindelof property in Finite and Countable Cartesian Products, Compositio Math., 23, 1971, 199-214.
  3. Willard, S., General Topology, 1970, Addison-Wesley Publishing Company.

___________________________________________________________________________________

\copyright \ \ 2012